A Few Preliminary Thoughts on #TheoryRevolt
Let me make it clear that I am definitely for theory in history, (as well as
an historicist approach to theory). Good on these good folk for reigniting interest
in what to me seems like an ongoing field of endeavour. I have a few quibbles,
and I’ve decided to write a blog piece on them. As will become clear, I’m not a
philosopher by trade, but I’ve always looked for ways to offer a theoretical
perspective to that which I’m doing. So, hopefully the following will be taken
in the spirit it is meant, as friendly, immanent critique of theoryrevolt.com And it will make most sense when read in conjunction with this.
Prologue: There
is a delicious irony in beginning this call to ‘decolonised history’ with an
appeal to Greek history. I will take It in the spirit of a joke, a prolegomenon
against itself. As someone interested in the classical world, and who feels
that (like someone else once said somewhere) anyone who isn’t applying the
study of the premodern world to their life and work is essentially living hand
to mouth, I enjoy a good classical allusion as well as the next person. But I
wonder if it was the most deft choice here…
But to the
content.
I.1 – Superficially,
this looks like Hayden White and Keith Jenkins, but it’s actually a different
challenge to theirs, one that I’m not sure I can accept as solving a
disciplinary problem. I am unsure what the difficulty with empiricism an sich is, given that its opposite,
rationalism (the opposite of empiricism is not theory), is equally problematic
as a basis for history. Rationalism, and its assumption that reason (not
observation) can be applied to the world to divine its fundamentally true
nature, gets us no further. For mine, the problem is neither empiricism nor
rationalism, but the fact that both are traditionally epistemological positions
that purport to offer access to truth. History might deal with what Jenkins
called ‘the traces of the before now’. But the weaving together of these might
not necessarily offer a ‘true’ account, but rather a preliminary position (not
quite a paradigm) that is open to endless contestation from other researchers
creating their own accounts from the traces of the before now. In some ways,
then, the attack on empiricism avoids the broader question of the
epistemological limits of historical analysis, even if it gestures towards it.
I.2 - The
first part of this is not entirely true, particularly given the recent spate of
articles and books problematising of the archive. As the Dothraki say, it is
known that the state archive is a suspect receptacle of the privileged but
partial exchanges of the powerful. Even the archives of the most friendly,
welcoming and harmless local club or association offers a partial version of
the past that accords with their unique perspective on the world, which is not
the same as offering ‘evidence’ of the truth of a particular position. We read archival
accounts not to patch together a functioning version of the complete truth
about the past. It is impossible to create a complete map of the past on a
scale of 1:1 (or indeed any other scale), just as it is impossible to retrieve
the rich diversity of human experiences of ‘the past’ (their present). Instead
we read archives out of a desire to become acquainted with how those in the
past represented themselves, their experiences and their priorities. These
perceptions can be theorised (or not) according to the methodological
preferences of the historian. But no-one I know sees the archival unproblematically
as the domain of the real and the home of the truth of social relations. They
do see it, however, as a useful place to find out what people in the past were
talking about and what notes they made about functioning within a set of social
relations. The archive, as has been long known, offers us doxa, not episteme.
The 2nd part, which suggests that
being a historian is performative (a strange adaptation of Butlerian ontology),
might be the case elsewhere, but wherever I am, historians are thinkers. They
are always concerned with the wider ramifications of that which they discuss,
and I’m yet to meet someone who simply views history and the writing of history
as techne. I’m surprised to see the concern about
historians writing for other historians, which is far from monolithically the
case. In some ways the demand that historians write for others (How often?
Always? Do all physicists and mathematicians have to write for us too?) actually
militates against a theoretically rooted perspective which requires some
assumed knowledge and is less likely to be immediately accessible than a
narrative history, which is arguably far more open to all comers.
I.3 –
Pushing at an open door here. And, far from constrained, I honestly often feel
overwhelmed by the choices I have to make about how to express my ideas. The
discipline is really quite open. Naturally journals, book series and even whole
presses may decide for any number of reasons to specialise in one approach or
another. This can facilitate methodological plurality or ghettoise research
into small discourse communities furiously agreeing with each other and
patrolling their borders. But the answer to this is to read more broadly and
facilitate cross fertilisation. Being cognisant of methodology is important for
other reasons too – it shows that a researcher is aware of the intellectual
heritage of their approach, and has not simply assumed that it is the only way
to discuss a particular problem.
I.4 The most
famous (and possibly the last) person seriously and consistently against
ontological realism was George Berkeley. I don’t think Berkeley’s anti
materialism is philosophically sustainable. At first I thought this was about
Baudrillard, the simulacrum and the desert of the real – good stuff for
historians to keep in mind when it comes to assessing the veracity of our
versions of the past. But in fact we’re back to the idiosyncratic crankiness
about empirical data and its supposed epistemological bankruptcy. The
‘tautology’ (not a tautology) is in fact a syllogistic fallacy. Proceeding via
an empiricist epistemology neither validates nor invalidates a particular
ontology. It doesn’t even require an acceptance of overarching truth
claims.
I.5 – I
haven’t experienced this (which of course is only an anecdotal experience). My
most theoretically ambitious works found the ‘highest profile’ journals for
homes (according to flawed but widely used metrics like ScImago). Reviewers are
not always fans of what they might call ‘clotted theory’, but they generally applaud
a theoretically informed history. I think this point confuses history as a
discipline with the neoliberal university, which certainly seeks to regulate
the work practices of its historians. To take a rough example, the ‘discipline’
would probably welcome a theoretically informed, 12 volume work that was
published all at once after 25 years of work. But no university in the world
would tolerate a ‘non-productive’ unit working on such a project. Hence the
constant dribble of results via journal articles.
As an
outsider to the US, I can’t comment on the position of the AHR, except to see
that it seems like a large, slow moving target that is easy to shoot at but
hard to bring down. I have no real interest in attacking or defending it, but I
will say that its mandate seems to be to publish material of general interest
to all historians. In some ways this might condemn it to offering the very best
of the lowest common denominator.
As for peer
review, I can only speak from my experience, but as the editor of a journal, I
can honestly say that all of our reviewers have worked in good faith to improve
the work of their colleagues. Many go well beyond what is required. Their major
complaint is generally that research is undercooked (ie hurried out because of
the pressure to publish – see my remark about the neo-liberal university), not
that it doesn’t fit an abstract template. If its scholarly, intelligible and
offers a new contribution, it will generally pass muster. Personally, having
been on the receiving end of dozens of reviews I can remember only one that was
calibrated to hurt. The others had intellectual and/or evidentiary differences that
they wanted to note, but which were not terminal for the research in the article.
I’ve also seen how the other systems work (hello Germany), where, at their
worst (and again this is not monolithically the case), leading lights are able
to offer patronage to client junior academics and help them get published.
Those without a powerful patron can end up relegated – or seeking refuge in the
anonymity of peer review in the Anglosphere, where their ideas might be treated
seriously without anyone prejudging their seniority.
I.6 – I’m
all for ‘rethinking the scholarly norms and forms of knowledge’ that enable
exclusions, but although ‘radically reimagining the use and applicability of
theory for history’ might be a Good Thing, it is not decolonisation.
Decolonisation is, (following Tuck and Yang) centred on the material struggle
for indigenous sovereignty and/or territorial autonomy or it is being used
metaphorically. And I tend to agree with them that ‘decolonisation is not a
metaphor’. Anyone who seriously believes that the AHR or any other journal can
decolonise society by being friendlier to theoretical approaches is at heart an
idealist. On the other side of this, I can imagine a strongly empiricist piece,
chock full of archival materials, that could very successfully challenge the
claims of Europeans to territorial sovereignty. Theory is not an intrinsically
decolonising force.
Correctly,
the authors say that the two distinct drives towards diversity and
decolonisation should not be confused. But again, as I’ve just indicated, empiricism
is neither intrinsically for or against decolonisation (or diversity for that
matter). More broadly, given the struggle for intellectual (and actual) space
by indigenous scholars around the world seeking legal and land justice, I’d be
more comfortable if Euro scholars stopped trying to demonstrate their
decolonising credibility, and in so doing crowding the field. Too often it
comes across as what has justly been called ‘settler moves to innocence.’ Being
seen as an ally in the struggle to decolonise seems like something that is
better bestowed than asserted.
I.7 – At
least where I’m from, the authors are pushing on an open door here. Integral to
any decent graduate training programme is exposure to and use of differing
theoretical approaches. It certainly is the bread and butter of Australian
history honours programmes. At Flinders University, for example, all of those
things mentioned by the authors are not only tolerated but explicitly taught as
possible approaches to our 4th year students looking to write new
histories. We are by now means exceptional in this regard.
I.8 – As with I.7, this must be a US thing, as it is
simply unrecognisable to me. The first essay my honours students write (via
White, Jenkins, Spivak, Said, Evans and others) is to answer the question ‘can
historians tell the truth about the past?’ And my PhD students are all, to a
greater or lesser degree grappling with figures like Agamben, Foucault, Marx,
Spivak, Baudrillard, plus more localised theorists that speak to their
immediate fields. They eschew neither the theoretical nor the empirical (itself
a false dichotomy).
By the way,
what students generally notice is that these theoreticians don’t just drop out
of the sky, but also need to be understood historically. At the risk of being
somewhat reductive, much of the theory of the past four decades, for example,
is a result of the ‘crisis of faith’ in the epistemic status of the truth
claims of the Marxist metanarrative, a development which has been in its own
way a type of intellectual Reformation of the Left. With intellectuals
(including historians) still trying to get their bearings, much is up for
grabs.
Not only is
history approached by many programmes that I’m familiar with in a
metahistorical fashion, the inclusion of theory in a dissertation is generally
seen as a sign of intellectual maturity, or at the least historiographical self-awareness.
I.9 – Not only
is this not my experience, but it also negates the earlier point made by the
authors, that lamented the obsession with methodology. And the separation of
data from theory is not a necessary condition of historiography. As a general
observation, I would say that many historians prefer to offer an overtly
theoretical orientation before dealing with the matter/s at hand – which may be
intellectual or material matters (or both). But this is not to stay that once
this orientation is offered the theory has vanished. Often, it provides the
underlying grammar and sense of every sentence written thereafter. In that
sense, theory is not simply a fancy introduction, nor is it simply a strainer
through which ‘facts’ are poured to capture the chunky bits. Rather, theory is
a structuring condition of all utterance in a work of history, guiding how
material and topoi are chosen and arranged to offer a verisimilar (but not
true) narrative of the past.
I.10 – It
is not necessarily a negative thing that there are specialist journals,
conferences and presses which deal with deeply theoretical issues, in the same
way that, while many foreground or include class, gender, economics, psychology
or sport in their histories elsewhere, there are places where scholars more
deeply committed to these approaches and themes can congregate and debate the
finer points. On the substantive point that ‘intellectual history is no more
likely to raise reflexive questions about historical epistemology and historiographic
norms than other professional subfields’, I’m not sure that this is borne out
by the differences between scholars who have really tussled with the
epistemological implications of, for example, Derrida, Lyotard or White and
those who haven’t. If the point is that even those who have aren’t clustered in
the narrow field of intellectual history still deal with epistemic issues, then
this seems right – see for example Gabrielle Spiegel. But I suspect that on a
per capita basis, historians dealing day in and day out with the history of
ideas and intellectual history are probably more aware of their position in the
epistemic conundrums of the postmodern challenge (for example) than others. But
it is self-evidently the case that some of the most interesting theorisations
of historical problems come from those who don’t work in the field of
intellectual history. In my own (far more modest) case, although most of my
work bears the traces of having visited archives, it is still a product of
ruthless, theoretically informed self-interrogation aimed at clarifying where I
stand intellectually (which, incidentally, might loosely be described as
phenomenological materialism).
I.11 ‘Time
and place, intention and agency, proximity and causality, context and chronology’.
There exists enormous disagreement about all of these things in the works of
history I read. Not because of any theoretical assumptions that have remained
unexamined. But because how to approach and present these things is up for
grabs. I note too the tendentious nature
of the phraseology here: ‘History’s anti-theoretical preoccupation with
empirical facts and realist argument nevertheless entails a set of
uninterrogated theoretical assumptions’. The statement is partially correct, in
the sense that refusing to directly address theoretical conundrums can be a
theory of history of its own. When pressed, this theory can come to the fore,
as perhaps best exemplified by Richard Evans’ In Defence of History. But sometimes (particularly in short journal
articles) it is a question of having other fish to fry or simply relying on the
reader’s ability to sense the theoretical orientation of the author through
word choice, historiographical engagements and the bibliographical / footnote
trail. It’s not always a fanatical ‘anti-theoretical preoccupation’. Equally,
however, it is not a single-minded obsession with matters theoretical alone
that drives a historian.
II.1 – This
can be dealt with quickly. Anyone who derides theory in this way cannot be
taken seriously. It is true that there is a debate between philosophy and
rhetoric on the question of truth dating back to Plato and the sophists. I’ve
more or less been on the side of the sophists since 1995 when I first learned
about this long conversation. No matter what the wilder eyed fringe dwellers of
the ‘digital humanities’ might say, history is not remotely a science, arguably
not even a social science. The ‘noble dream of a pure science’ has well and
truly left the building. Most historians are perfectly content to offer their
best understanding of the past and welcome the cut and thrust of debate to try
and adjudicate on the uncertainty. Our best hopes are of verisimilitude, not
Truth.
II.2 –
There is nothing to dispute here. The past in its entirety is irretrievable
because it never existed as a coherent whole. The narratives we create as
historians can cleave to old narratives or can represent the unfolding of new
ways of understanding ourselves and that which has come before us. But they are
narratives that offer our best reflections on privileged (by us) elements of
the before now. As Croce and a thousand others have said, just what we
privilege as worthy of investigation reflects both our social coordinates and
theoretical / philosophical priorities.
II.3 – I’m
not sure that theory was really seen as aberrant, even in the 1990s, by
practitioners of history as a whole. Troubling, yes and dismissed out of hand
by some who just weren’t up for the challenge. But mostly, ‘high theory’
settled back into the pack in the same way that social history, microhistory, diplomatic history, gender
history, or transnational history has. If pushed, most would admit that the
long dark night of the soul visited upon the discipline between the 1970s and
2000s were of enormous benefit to the discipline, rather than a wrong turn. In
the end, however, a stalemate emerged, (a bit like the Sonderweg debate in
German history) where either the insights were accepted or not. If accepted,
they were worked into new approaches. And the recalcitrants went about their
business, secure in their self-understanding of their work.
II.4 – I
think that the least often use of Foucault is as an empirical study of
penology.
II.5 – This
seems unrepresentative of how theory is used. Particularly of Marxism and
gender, which are theoretical orientations that tend to permeate every fibre of
a work written by historians committed to these positions. Take gender for
example. Almost every work I’ve read grappling with gender issues has implicitly
or explicitly tackled the challenge of Butlerian notions of performativity in a
way that deeply problematises ‘the sex/gender distinction or the fixity of the
m/f opposition’. Not necessarily to agree with Butler, but to tackle it as an
intellectual proposition to be discussed historically.
II.6 – I
presume the authors are talking about Richard Evans here. It’s fair to say that
some came to an intellectually honest, deeply considered position that the
epistemological challenge of the 90s was wrong headed. This was the case for
historians on both left and right, both of which were heavily invested in
maintaining the epistemic integrity of their guiding metanarratives. If there
was no Truth to be recuperated historically, if the Truth of their position was
not universally applicable, then what were they to do? For many, Lyotard’s
incredulity towards metanarratives invalidated their strongly held conviction
that they were able to reveal the True nature (and trajectory of history). The
spectre of history stripped of its guiding teleology stopped many from staring
for too long into the abyss. This to me doesn’t look like a dismissal of
theory. It looks like an intellectual commitment to a theory of history that
sought to salvage the possibility of a traditional approach to epistemology –
that is, to establish the best way to ascertain Truth, rather than to place the
access (or existence) of Truth (and therefore the knowledge of Truth) in
question.
II.7 – As
the immediate above argues, the worry was not about the distorting imposition
of fixed ideological categories, but rather a desire to maintain them that
prompted many to reject the radical epistemic challenge of post modernity.
II.8 – OK
so this looks like an oblique reference to Derrida. To be sure, there were those
that simply maintained that the command ‘pass the salt’ generally ended up with
a result that was not the passing of pepper. It is probably fair criticism that
Derrida (unlike Foucault, Butler, Spivak, and numerous others) found little
long-term purchase in history – partly because deconstruction was partially
disarmed by thoughtful (by no means dismissive) responses by historians such as
Gabrielle Spiegel, who pointed us to the ‘social logic of a text’ and how
meaning might be tentatively imputed by careful excavation of the social
conditions enabling all utterance. Said too reminded us in his underread World ,Text and the Critic that textual
production is also a material act, not simply rarefied utterance. I’m not a committed fan of Derrida, but this is
not due to a ‘disregard for the vagaries of language’, which are all too
evident when transposing concepts and terms across time and space. Rather, I do
think that a deep immersion in the texts of the past can offer a guiding sense
of the prevailing concerns and discursive norms of discourse communities
located in previous times. Understandings garnered through this deep immersion
are always tentative and preliminary. But they probably amount to more than
language games. They have some purchase, but do not reveal a lost True Past.
III.1 – I
agree, but think the authors are pushing at an open door here. Everywhere I
look I see ‘serious engagement with critical theories of self, society and
history.’ Who are these unthinking historians, mindlessly assembling facts in
the belief that they are reconstructing the Truth about the past? I just don’t
know them. ‘The guild’ (more a loose agglomeration than a closed shop)
endlessly interrogates its claims to knowledge and to Truth, critiques the
nature and useability of facts as evidence, quarrels incessantly over causal
connections and chronology. Sometimes this occurs in the context of positing
overtly a theory of the operation of social relations and of the emergence of
different permutations of the experience of life over time and space.
Sometimes, the assumptions are implicit and not expounded at length. Both might
well be critical histories, but only one would probably be recognised as
therorised history.
III.2 – I
am certainly all for elaborating the ‘worldly stakes of an historiographical
intervention’. Quite often this is done overtly in theoretically informed
history, but more accurately ‘theoretically informed history’ that elaborates
the worldly stakes of its concerns is often produced by historians that, in the
face of the radical epistemic challenge of postmodernity, have maintained a
guiding teleological understanding of the nature of history and its True
direction. Arguably, the desire to link ‘non-contiguous, non-proximate
arrangements, processes, and forces that may be separated by continents or
centuries’ can be explained as a desire to maintain the theoretical coherence
of a metanarrative of the past that is required to support teleological
presuppositions. Those not sharing the same assumptions might dismiss these
tenuous causal chains as leaps of faith. Those sharing the same telos, however,
might find themselves convinced by the eloquent solution it offers to a
paradigmatic contradiction that troubles their understanding of the True nature
of societies, both past and present.
III.3 – The
first sentence neatly outlines the epistemic challenge of postmodernity.
However the last sentence remains elusive, in that it does not point to a
solution or even a method to deal with that challenge beyond ‘do theory’. In saying that ‘critical history points
beyond the false opposition between empiricist induction and rationalist
deduction, and historicist description and transhistorical abstraction’, what
is not said is what it points to. Does it point to a better way of ascertaining
the True direction / nature of history? Or does it point to the illegitimacy /
inability / futility of empiricist and rationalist attempts to find an
underlying True pattern or trajectory of past events? Or do the authors believe
that an ultimate answer to this question doesn’t matter, providing it is
derived critically?
III.4 – I
was wondering when they would get around to tackling the relationship between
facts and Truth. Incidentally, I don’t think that the equation of facts with truth
implies a logical contradiction created
by an inability to account for change over time. Even Hegel all those years ago
differentiated between the slaughterbench of history (facts) and the Truth of
the Weltgeist, to offer a neat way to
account for the way in which individual facts need not align with a posited
narration of history’s True direction.
But to deal
with the more substantive point, I can’t recall any historian who has claimed that
facts were not socially mediated or that modes of thought, categories of
analysis and explanations of the nature of reality were not products of a
particular historical moment. Admittedly, this is easier to spot in works
dealing with periods or places that are not close to the present era /
proximate region of the historian, where the social assumptions of historical
actors are still shared by the jobbing historian who profess to analyse them.
But when push comes to shove, historians are more apt to say ‘that an
historical actor (or less accurately a whole society) believed something to be
the case, than immediately agreeing with this view. This was all dealt with so
long ago by those protesting about Whiggish history and the imputing of social
values to facts.
The bolder
point about facts and Truth to my mind is that factoids remain indispensable to
history, in the sense that driving towards a verisimilar account of the before
now must draw on the traces of the before now and seek to assess what they can
tell us. Not what they can tell us about the underlying nature of reality (an
underlying nature which may not exist but is at the very least irretrievable),
however, but, what they can reveal about how people have experienced the
material fact of their existence and their immersion in a particular social
context. Again, how we choose, arrange and interpret the these ‘facts’ is open
to contestation by others who see different explanations of how people
negotiated the world. Assuming that rival accounts take the available ‘facts’
seriously in their attempt to create a verisimilar account of the past, there
are few grounds to falsify rival accounts. But it is equally probable that
these accounts will become less and less satisfactory to historians as the
social conditions and concomitant assumptions enabling the material fact of
literary production change.
II.5 – Only
furious agreement here. ‘Context’ is always short hand for something more
unwieldy with specific temporal and spatial coordinates, as it seems to me most
historians understand. To my mind, elaborating context requires the kind of
reading of the social logic of texts championed by Spiegel.
III.6 – I
can only assume that all historians are self-reflexive, in the sense that they take
inordinate care to say that which they intend to say (notwithstanding the
difficulty of unintentional seepages that can be uncovered through contrapuntal
readings of historiographical texts, and the Derridean challenge, death of the
author etc). Confession time for me – I’m not a fan of gonzo history, in which
the valiant struggle of the historian to overcome their baser self through
their interaction with their object of study is foregrounded. Such performative sublation
leaves me cold. I prefer my history without long passages agonising over
subject position, because generally I take it as read that everyone comes from
somewhere and brings their own unique personal engagements and commitments to
their analysis and writing. If I can spot it, so much the better. But if I
can’t, then that’s OK too. There are obvious moments where caveats, disclaimers,
declarations and even self-disqualifications are necessary (see, for example, my above doubts
about settler historians claiming to be decolonising), but these don’t extend
so far that they should go much beyond the preface (or perhaps introduction)
of a monograph or the first footnote of an article.
Note though
that is a stylistic preference. I entirely accept that historians must be
cognisant of their subject position, their epistemic and political assumptions
and what implications these have for their work. Others will of course disagree
and prefer to see the cogito at the centre of the narrative. For me, however,
if I want Hunter S Thompson, I’ll read Hunter S Thompson.
II.7. Good
old Croce. This is of course entirely acceptable, yet how it is framed or
emplotted is a matter of both tactics and intent. As this is my blog, I will
use my own work to explain what I mean here.
My last
book was about expulsions of unwanted
populations from Germany between 1871 and 1914. The first draft had a long
preamble in which I discussed the ‘uncanny returns, haunting traces and
spectral forces’ of such expulsions, given the current processes of 'cleansing' nation-states of ostensibly unauthorised arrivals and other marginalised groups; not least
in Australia, where asylum seekers arriving by boat where / are being housed in concentration
camps in the Pacific, to ensure their definitive and very public removal from Australia. It was a long, angry, densely footnoted preamble with scandalous examples from the 21st
century and it arguably shed contemporary light on my research. Before I submitted the
manuscript, I deleted it. Why? Not because I had suddenly become less
interested or angered by these contemporaneous atrocities of the liberal Rechtsstaat, but because I didn’t want
the book to be read as an extended allegory, even thought the parallels more or
less worked at a superficial level. I also have real problems with forced transtemporal
comparisons which I think are usually metaphorical, and generally not
structural. That’s not to say that I don’t think history can be described
structurally, only that the epiphenomena produced by any given structure is
particular to its context, and thus not likely to repeat itself.
In fact, I
didn’t have to include my angry prologue, because almost every reviewer noted
the loose current parallels, but also treated the book for what it primarily
was, namely an attempt to find out how a different society had dealt with a set
of problems that were recognisable to a contemporary audience.
III.8 –
Given what I’ve just said, I’m not sure I agree with the goal of disabling ‘the very logic of
past and present, now and then, here and there, us and them. I assume that this
is meant as an anti-Manichaean gesture, an attempt to break down false binaries,
rather than the application of some kind of metaphysical embrace of multiverse
theory. I’m all for getting ridding of unhelpful categories of analysis. But
collapsing the differences between the before now and the present seems to be
unhelpful. Because as the authors say elsewhere, this would refuse the
possibility for accounting for changes over time (changes occur, just how they
are emplotted teleologically by historians and the possibility of establishing
the epistemic grounds for understanding these changes is of course up for
grabs).
Far from
denaturalising existing arrangements, breaking down the distinctions between
then and now actually naturalises the current order by incorporating it into a
more amorphous ‘always and everywhere’. The ‘actual social order’ described in
this point might better be seen as the ‘current social order’ – different to other
social orders (and future ones). Giving up the tools we have to distinguish
between them disarms us.
III.9 – I
agree that intervening in public debates and political struggles is important –
even core business for intellectuals. There might arguably be a moral responsibility
to offer back to the community a tangible return for the enormous investment
made in our research. This does not, of course, mean that those who pay the
piper get to call the tune. The precise nature of our interventions should
ideally reflect our understanding of the nature of things. We have no
responsibility, that is, to support the interests of social, economic and
political power.
That said,
we should understand that unless we want to create Plato’s Republic, (which I
absolutely would not recommend), we want to pause before imposing ourselves by
fiat on political debate. My expertise on the Kaiserreich, for example, may mean that I am no better placed to analyse
our current desperate state than others who share my curiosity in the present
world. I have a fairly elaborate understanding of how I think the world works, and
I even try to convince people that I’m right through political action
sometimes. But I was always impressed when Noam Chomsky admitted that he could
find no grounds to link his linguistics with his politics. History is not the
same thing as linguistics, but as I’ve already said, I am suspicious of
transtemporal analogies reliant on a shallow historical comparisons.
Particularly when they make us deaf to contemporary exigencies.
One caveat here: this is less true of those working in the field of contemporary history, where the links between past and present are demonstrable.
While we’re talking about what a contribution
might look like, we might, for that matter, also think twice before using our
training to exclude or deride those that do not share our vocabulary or frame
of intellectual reference. Interventions that amount to nothing more than
patrolling the language used to describe the nature of things by those who
haven’t been inculcated in the finer points of intellectual etiquette are (for
my money) counterproductive Besserwisserei.
For mine, an intervention looks for ways
to build bridges and new forms of social collaboration, not ever more
exhaustive lines of demarcation.
III.10 –
Yes, understanding the existing (and perhaps exiting) world is useful, even
important, however, I’m also happy to see a more focused immersion in the
traces of the before now (ie old stuff) and the relics of the period of our particular specialisation.
And what if a historian just feels unqualified to enter into nuanced debate about
contemporary fiscal policy in Latin America, because they work on art history
of ninth century somewhere or other? It would be wrongheaded to assume they had a
unique insight into the contemporary world.
The
committed intellectual, au fait with
the intricacies of the present and ready to comment or act on them, is a
treasure to be sure, however, it’s not compulsory to be both scholar and
political pundit, policy wonk or vanguard of the revolution. As I’ve already
said, even though I’m not dismissive of all historical accounts that assert enduring
historical structures, I’m not a fan of historiography that is simple politico-moral
allegory. It would be a poor use of theory to use it as a sophisticated mystification
of the differing structural and epiphenomenonal features of discrete historical
contexts. And given my doubts about the epistemic basis of metanarratives that
posit an underlying directionality to history, I find it hard to extrapolate
that which I have studied about the past to prophesise about the future. I have
my convictions and largely act in accordance with them, but I rarely argue that
they stem from my study of the past.
Coda: Yeah,
nah. Historians are not like interpreters of dreams, because (and I say this
with the full conviction of someone who once worked in an esoteric bookshop),
analysing dreams is a complete and utter waste of time. And the metaphor doesn’t
even make sense. The dream interpreters that prosper are the Delphic oracles,
deliberately vague enough for everyone to impute their own meaning. Trust me, I watched a tarot card reader do it for 4 hours a day. The
interpretation of the dream must not make sense, so that the dreamer has room
to assume that their assumptions are right (and that the interpreter really
does have access to a higher order skill). The historian works in the other
direction. If we can’t move beyond the Delphic and empty turn of phrase, then we’re
not really doing anything of social value. We're just pretending to be Zizek. And how many Zizeks do we actually need?
This does
not mean that theoretically driven history must be conventional. At its best it
is daring, innovative, and profoundly unsettling. To that extent, I gladly
accept the invitation to interpretative and political innovation. Hooray for theory! And hooray for this renewed call to embrace it! But not at
the expense of a false dichotomy between empiricism and theory or at the cost of coherence and intelligibility.
Comments
Post a Comment